Methodological Diversity
The preceding sessions of
our seminar have started to highlight how IR as an academic discipline lack of
self-reflexivity in diverse respects. Obviously failing to offer much varying
perspectives in terms of race, gender, social class, geographies, and
histories, IR, as practiced in the West in general and in the the US in
particular, may also have failed to comprehensively engage with the debates of
adjacent—sometimes extensively used within the field—disciplines. This is the
case, PTJ suggests, with philosophy of science, which in fact bears by essence
a foundational character to any scientific enterprise.
Indeed, one cannot help
but notice that, when philosophers of science are called upon in IR, their
journey is oftentimes presented as a Lakatos’ progressing research program: everything
fits rather neatly from Descartes to Weber, Kuhn, Popper, and is eventually
harmonized and articulated in KKV. PTJ points out that these “opportunistic
raids into foreign scholarly territory” have eclipsed the demarcation problem
at the core of the actual debates. If PTJ proposes a (Weber-inspired) definition
of science in the IR context (he later argues that “international studies” need
not be a science, see PTJ 2015), the principal innovation is to uncover the
lack of coherence in the field’s organization—if one consider carefully the ontology,
epistemology, and methodology of different approaches—and to offer an alternative
typology (p. 37-40).
At the crossroads of
mind-world dualism and monism (concepts that could maybe be reversed: to be discussed
in class), and phenomenalism and transfactualism, PTJ brings out 4 ideal-types,
equally “scientific” but based on different evaluative criteria. His typology is sometimes counter-intuitive: for instance, analyticism is illustrated with the work of Ken Waltz, notorious
father of neorealism (in the old typology; PTJ is challenged by Humphreys on this point). The extended metaphor of
the democratic peace theory in different ideal-types illustrates the potential narrowness
of interpretation of science if one of them holds an undue monopoly (namely,
neopositivism). Indeed, many seminars in IR theory across the US would use
Green et al. (2001)—which strongly criticize the use of pooled cross-sectional
time series using the MIDs dataset so as to validate democratic peace theory—to
demonstrate ongoing methodological debates in IR. Instead, it should be described
as mere “discussion about methods for achieving neopositivist goals” (p. 68). The
four scientific ways through which one can study world politics in fact respond to
different philosophies (ontological) and use distinctive methodologies.
As Suganami suggests, could
PTJ's propositions be rearranged in 3 categories, as their inherent and original character
rests on “the questions they ask” and the interests they reflect rather than their
“philosophical foundations”? Why would PTJ’s typology overlook the
myth-historical character of IR, along with other parameters, as Michel
implies? Is PTJ’s approach unsympathetic
to engagement (Wight) or forgetful of major components in his ideal-types (Sylvester)?
It can be noted that the literature PTJ engages with is American (comprehensively),
Anglo-Saxon (in majority), and Western (quasi-exclusively?). Would his
ideal-types have been different had the research been extended to more non-Western
philosophers of science and social scientists?
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
<< Home