Monday, April 18, 2011

Scholarship and (not “versus”) Activism

Flyvbjerg’s case for phronetic research—one explicitly driven by values and engaged with the world outside academia—is compelling. He summarizes the core of this approach in “the following three value-rational questions: (1) Where are we going? (2) Is this desirable? (3) What should be done?” He adds, “Phronetic researchers can see no neutral ground, no ‘view from nowhere,’ for their work” (61). The scholar, in other words, need not apologize for having a stance. Though this approach is refreshing, it leaves me confused about where the distinction lies between scholarship and activism.

Flyvbjerg’s account of his involvement in the Aalborg development debate is instructive. He finds, like so many city planners do, that the Chamber of Commerce wields disproportionate power over the elected and duly appointed officials overseeing land-use planning. (I know planners in the Denver metropolitan area who have had the exact same complaint.) He laments that the Chamber pushes hard for catering to, and thus encouraging the growth of, automobile traffic.

Clearly, Flyvbjerg has a stance himself on the issues being debated in Aalborg:

With a roughly 50 percent increase in bicycle and public transportation in downtown Aalborg during the first decade of the Aalborg Project, and without the projected 35 percent decline in automobile traffic, but an increase instead, … the pressure on downtown road space has produced harmful effects on environment, traffic safety, and traffic flow…. Thus the losers in the struggle over the Aalborg Project were… virtually all of the city’s and the region’s half-million inhabitants plus many visitors (153).

From my experience working on transportation issues, I can attest that many people would not see increased car traffic in downtown Aalborg as a bad thing. Some would prefer this scenario over seeing all of those cars go to shopping malls in the distant suburbs; others would point to the reality that with so many people driving cars, planners must do what is possible to accommodate them and keep the motor-vehicle traffic flowing smoothly.

Flyvbjerg’s partisan stance caused me to wonder how different Flyvbjerg’s writing and scholarship would be if he were hired by the Danish Cyclists’s Federation (mentioned on 157) or an environmental NGO to write public relations material for them. Flyvbjerg would probably readily accept that he has a stance, since to the phronetic researcher there is “no neutral ground” (61). Still, he does seem to be making some claim to having a view of the situation that is closer to the truth than the view of the Chamber of Industry and Commerce: to him, the headline “Aalborg’s Best Customers Come Driving in Cars” is “misleading” (150).

Flyvbjerg does attempt to discuss what makes a scholar’s stance or interpretation more valid. He argues that a focus on values does not mean an anything-goes relativism—“one interpretation is not just as good as another” (130); yet the main criterion seems to be whether “a better interpretation demonstrates the previous interpretation to be ‘merely‘ interpretation.” He concedes that “social science and philosophy have not yet identified criteria by which an ultimate interpretation and a final grounding of values and facts can be made” (131). Some phronetic scholarship is better than others, then, but what makes it so is, apparently, difficult to make explicit.

In helping the reader better understand phronetic social science, Flyvbjerg provides other examples (162-65), including the book Promiscuities: A Secret History of Female Desire by Naomi Wolf. In describing this book, Flyvbjerg calls it “less academic, though still scholarly informed”—so he is making a distinction between academic and non-academic writing, though the word “less” implies that it is a continuum, not a bright line. I happen to be a big fan of Wolf because of an earlier work of hers, The Beauty Myth. This latter book is extremely thoroughly researched, yet I would probably put it in the category of popular nonfiction rather than scholarship (similar to his assessment of Promiscuities), though I have a hard time pinpointing why. Perhaps it is because the book is intended for a general audience, not an academic one. Yet Flyvbjerg argues strenuously for engaging with the real world, not staying cloistered in the academic domain: “dialogue with groups outside of academia… is at the heart of phronetic social science” (157-58). The audience, then, is apparently not the decisive factor in determining what makes scholarship. Promiscuities is now on my summer reading list, and a quick look at the few pages available online reveals that a portion of it is devoted to autobiographical material related to Wolf’s own adolescence. Is this what makes it less academic and more pop? Not to Flyvbjerg—to him, “Doing narrative” (136) is among his methodological guidelines (chapter 9). If Wolf’s writing is not scholarship to Flyvbjerg, then, it is neither because of the audience nor because of personal narrative.

My questions about phronetic social science, then, remain unanswered. If scholarship is driven by values (see, e.g., 130), what makes it scholarship rather than advocacy? What is the difference between scholarship and non-scholarly nonfiction? If social scientists are not only free to take a stance but perhaps even obligated to do so, what distinguishes the validity of their interpretation from the validity of any partisan on an issue?As Namalie suggests, maybe we all need to learn to be more comfortable with such ambiguity.

6 Comments:

Blogger SonjaKelly said...

Suzanne, your post is so interesting in light of Kate's below. What would Weber say to Flyvbjerg's project to imbue social science with phronesis? In a sense, does Flyvbjerg's project fly in the face of the distinction between politics and science?

On the other hand, were we fooling ourselves to think it was possible to do social science without considering context and therefore normative value?

Very much looking forward to our class discussion today.

9:14 AM  
Blogger adabunny said...

I am also very confused by how flibbertygibbet decides what is academic and what is not, given his proclivity for self-reflexive (is that redundant?) narrative.

However, I disagree with Efe. I don't see why this shouldn't be considered social science -- at least for the reasons Efe mentioned.

I am left wondering: if power is experienced -- not something static and exogenous -- then power exists everywhere (duh)... but does social science then have to focus on certain experiences of power over others? For instance, a family is a great locus of power dynamics. But is a study of that à la chapter 9 considered Social Science (capital S)? Or is it more psychology? Does it matter?

I liked flibbertygibbet's book. Granted, I missed the class discussion, so I am fairly certain I did not understand all the nuances of the book that we generally cover in class.
I especially liked the discussion of Habermas and Foucault. It solidifies a lot of what we've been reading in both CoI and Social Theory.

7:48 AM  
Anonymous Ela said...

I think scholarship and activism are two distinct roles, but just because they are distinct does not make them mutually exclusive. Some scholars with value commitments are bad researchers, others are not. Some scholars with *no* value commitments are bad researchers, others are not. Scholarship can be evaluated on other criteria -- as it often is. Whether you're an activist or not, scholarship is still subject to peer review and other non-activists ask you to back up your claims. You either do or you don't.

Consider, for example, Dani Rodrik's book, "One Economics, Many Principles." By Flyvbjerg's standards, the book is a work of scholarship activism that engages with the real world outside of academe. Rodrik addresses the questions, "Where are we going?" "Is it desirable?" and "What should be done?" He emphasizes the need for economists to pay attention to the particulars of specific contexts when designing development projects. He even (gasp!) combines university research and teaching with consulting gigs. And yet, would anyone call him a bad economist? I recall that Efe even once remarked he was a great economist.So, perhaps engaging with the world and asking "Where are we going?" "Is it desirable?" and "What should be done?" isn't so bad after all.

Comments?

9:23 PM  
Blogger Efe Sevin said...

Well, deRaismes let me try to clarify my point about F9 and social science. First of all, urban planning is not a social science. It is just a combination of architecture and to an extent geography. Secondly, I am offended by his claims about social science, where he equates science as a claim-producing machine. Social science is no longer about exploring, describing, analyzing social phenomena, but is about gaining leverage in political scene. Ela, practicing what you research, or (maybe more in Rodrik's case) studying a practice can be done in a systematic way. Rodrik answers 'should' and 'desirable' questions in macro-economics terms, rather then using numbers to support his position. (So, which comes first? research or position is the question).

10:51 AM  
Anonymous Ela said...

Efe, it seems that we both agree that that are good and bad ways to do research that engages with the world. Discrediting Flyvbjerg shouldn't lead to discrediting all scholars who do research that engages with the world. In this sense, I think Flyvbjerg's point is well taken.

7:13 AM  
Blogger Efe Sevin said...

Ela, I definitely agree. Most of my research is based on 'real world', case studies. I even do single case studies of place branding projects that I professionally work on. Yet, F9's recommendations point to a bad,inadequate, and to an extent ethically questionable way of conducting research.

11:17 AM  

Post a Comment

<< Home